WHAT DOES BEING AN “ARISTOTELIAN” REALLY MEAN?
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.21814/eps.2.1.98Keywords:
Aristotle, Aristotelian, Aristotelianism, ethics, political philosophy, methodologyAbstract
The present paper presents two main arguments: 1) The meanings of terms like “(neo-) Aristotelian” or “Aristotelianism” have become extremely ambiguous in the present literature of ethics and political philosophy. These terms have even become confusing rather than being descriptive or explanatory. The following questions seem to have no proper answers: Who is actually “Aristotelian,” or “neo-Aristotelian,” to what extent and for what reasons? What does “(neo-) Aristotelian” really mean? 2) In order to give some clues to properly answer these questions, as its second argument, the present paper attempts to define the essential methodological characteristics of Aristotelian ethical/political exploration. To be called as an “Aristotelian,” a research should start from the methodological peculiarities of Aristotle’s practical philosophy that make a research “Aristotelian” rather than “Kantian” or “Hegelian.” In the second part of the paper, these peculiarities are defined as methodological prudence and medical dialectics, which are characteristic aspects of Aristotelian way of inquiry regarding ethics and political philosophy.
References
Allard-Nelson, S. K. (2004). An Aristotelian Approach to Ethical Theory: The Norms of Virtue. New York: The Edwin Mellen Press.
Aristotle. (1984). The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes, 2 Vols. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Aristotle. (1985). Nicomachean Ethics. Trans.Terece Irwin. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
Aristotle. (1992). Eudemian Ethics: Books I, II and VIII. Trans. Michael Woods. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Aristotle. (1995). Politics: Books I and II. Trans. Trevor J. Saunders. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oseo/instance.00259304
Aristotle. (1997). Politics: Books VII and VIII. Trans. Richard Kraut. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oseo/instance.00259313
Aristotle. (1999). Politics: Books V and VI. Trans. David Keyt. Oxford: Oxford University Press,. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oseo/instance.00259310
Aristotle. (2005). Politics: Books III and IV. Trans. Richard Robinson. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ball, T. (1978). “Two Concepts of Coercion.” Theory and Society, 5: 97-112. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01880862
Benhabib, S. (1988). “Judgment and the Moral Foundations of Politics in Arendt’s Thought.” Political Theory, 16: 29-51. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591788016001003
Bodéüs, R. (1993). The Political Dimensions of Aristotle’s Ethics. Trans. Jan Edward Garrett. New York: SUNY.
Buckle, S. (2002). “Aristotle’s Republic or, Why Aristotle’s Ethics is Not Virtue Ethics.” Philosophy, 77: 565-595. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819102000463
Crisp, R. and Slote, M.(1997). eds. Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Frank, J. (2005). Democracy of Distinction: Aristotle and the Work of Politics. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Gaukroger, S. (2006). The Emergence of a Scientific Culture: Science and the Shaping of Modernity, 1210-1685. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199296446.001.0001
Herman, B. (1993). The Practice of Moral Judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hinchman, L. P. (1984). “The Origins of Human Rights: A Hegelian Perspective.” Western Political Quarterly, (34)1: 7-31. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/106591298403700103
Höffe, O. (1997). “Outlook: Aristotle or Kant-Against a Trivial Alternative.” In How Natural is the Ethical Law?, eds. Paul Cobben and Ludwig Heyde, 1-19. Tilburg: Tilburg University Press.
Hursthouse, R. (1999). On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Jacobs, J. (2004). Aristotle’s Virtue: Nature, Knowledge and Human Good. New York: Peter Lang Publishing.
Jager, W. 1957. “Aristotle’s Use of Medicine as Model of Method in his Ethics.” Journal of Hellenistic Studies, 77: 54-61. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/628634
Karatani, K. (2003). Transcritique: On Kant and Marx. Trans. Sabu Kohso. Cambridge: MIT Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/6897.001.0001
King, R. H. (1990). “Old Problems/New Departures: American Political Thought since 1960.” The History Teacher, 24(1): 99-112. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/494209
Korsgaard, C.(1996). “From Duty and for the Sake of the Noble.” In Aristotle, Kant and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty, eds. Stephen Engtrom and Jennifer Whiting, 203-236. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Linden, H. van der (1988). Kantian Ethics and Socialism. Indianapolis: Hackett.
Lloyd, G.E.R. (1968). “The Role of Medical and Biological Analogies in Aristotle’s Ethics.” Phronesis, 1: 68-83. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1163/156852868X00047
MacIntrye, A. (1984). After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. 2nd ed. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Mantague, P. (1992). “Virtue Ethics: A Qualified Success Story.” American Philosophical Quarterly, (29)1: 53-61.
Mcaleer, S. (2007). “An Aristotelian Account of Virtue Ethics: An Essay in Moral Taxonomy.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 88: 208-225. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0114.2007.00287.x
Mill, J. S. (1974). A System of Logic in Collected Works, Vol. VIII. Toronto: Toronto University Press.
Miller, F. D. Jr. (2007). “Aristotelian Statecraft and Modern Politics.” In Aristotle’s Politics Today, eds. Lenn E. Goodman and Robert B. Talisse, 13-32. New York: SUNY Press.
Miller, F. D. Jr. (1995). Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle’s Politics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Mulhall, S. and Swift, A. (1992). Liberals and Communitarians. Cambridge: Blackwell Publishers.
Nussbaum, M. C. (1994).Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Nussbaum, M. C. (1999). “Virtue Ethics: A Misleading Category?” Journal of Ethics, (3)3: 163-201. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1009877217694
Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511817915
O’Neill, O. (1989).Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Putnam, R. A. (1988). “Reciprocity and the Virtues.” Ethics 98: 379-389. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1086/292947
Salkever, S.(1990). Finding the Mean: Theory and Practice in Aristotle’s Political Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Sherman, N. (1997). Making a Necessity of Virtue: Aristotle and Kant on Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511624865
Simpson, P. (1992). “Contemporary Virtue Ethics and Aristotle.” Review of Metaphysics, 45: 503-54.
Smith, T. W. (2001). Revaluing Ethics: Aristotle’s Dialectical Pedagogy. New York: SUNY.
Wallach, J. R. (1992). “Contemporary Aristotelianism.” Political Theory, (20)1: 613-641. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591792020004004
Wood, E. M. and Wood, N. (1978). Class Ideology and Ancient Political Theory: Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle in their Social Context. New York: Oxford University Press.
Yack, B. (1986). The Longing for Total Revolution: Philosophic Sources of Social Discontent from Rousseau to Marx and Nietzsche. Princeton: Princeton University Press.